The Good, the Right, and Theology

by Peter Daniel Haworth on March 22, 2011 · 2 comments <span>Print this article</span> Print this article

in Short

Many FPR readers will enjoy Thaddeus Kozinski’s fine article, “The Good, the Right, and Theology.” This elucidates a theological-traditionalist account of ethics, and it offers an alternative resolution to contemporary debate (e.g., between Hadley Arkes and Matthew O’Brien) about competing eudaimonistic and deontological theories in moral philosophy. It was recently published in ANAMNESIS, A Journal for the Study of Tradition, Place, and ‘Things Divine.’ Here is an excerpt:

Theology has been a curious non-interlocutor in most public debates among conservative theists regarding how best to defend the objectivity, intelligibility, and communicability of moral truths and their application to contemporary legal issues, such as racial discrimination, human rights, and abortion. One such debate occurred recently on the pages of On the Square and Public Interest. (For a summary of and commentary on the debate, see Micah Watson’s A Tale of Two Philosophers). The main issue of the debate was not the content of basic moral principles, but their epistemological, ontological, and rhetorical aspects: the fundamental structure of moral thinking and judgment, its relation to what precisely is being thought about and judged, and the most reasonable and effective mode of public ethical and legal discourse. The two interlocutors agreed “that the source of morality is human nature, that human nature is essentially a rational nature, and that moral truths are discoverable through reason apart from revelation,” and they both condemned the moral evil of racial discrimination. What they were at odds about is exactly why this or any evil act is evil, and what makes an act good and a moral principle true. The question comes down to the precise ontic and epistemic character of “ought.”…

As it seems to me, this debate is a scuffle in an ongoing human feud, begun back in the wranglings between the ancient Stoics and Epicureans. It is a war between “two rival versions of moral enquiry,” to use MacIntyre’s expression, eudaimonism and deontologism: an ethics of happiness, flourishing, virtues, eros, and the good, versus an ethics of self-sacrifice, duty, law, agape, and the right. This feud is not going to end any time soon, at least not without some mediation, by a third, peace-making interlocutor.

As I said at the outset, theology, unlike in the ancient debates, has not been an interlocutor in this and virtually all other academic and public discussions of ethics and politics. Sure, the theologian is allowed to have his say, but he is barred from ever having an authoritative say, from being one of those insiders whose deliberations and speculations are to become an integral part of “public reason.” The theologians have a quite compelling story, the philosophers and public policy folks admit, but we need a story more appropriate, more “true,” for our pluralistic, secular, political culture. However, when dealing with the foundations of ethics, the Christian theologian’s story is not just one story among others—it is one that must be read by everyone, for it is meant for everyone. It is ultimately everyone’s story. Moreover, as Radical Orthodoxy has shown, the ostensibly a-theological, secular stories that automatically pass the muster of public reason are nothing if not theologically implicated, even if only implicitly. Now, although the Christian story is everyone’s story, only a very select audience has heard it in its entirety, believed it fully, and made it a model for their own life-stories. Yet, even for the unbeliever, the theologian’s story has clear and arguable logical, ethical, philosophical, legal and political ramifications and components, just as the “non-theological” stories have implicit yet robust theological moorings. Let those who have ears—that is, those who have taken out their old and decrepit, modernist, Enlightenment earplugs—hear: “We are all theologians now.”

Kozinski’s theological-traditionalist argument is further developed in the article. Here one will find a serious critique of modern Kantian attempts (e.g., those of Hadley Arkes and, albeit not mentioned in the article, Robert George) to develop a ‘publicly reasonable’ moral philosophy.

 

 

 

 

{ 2 comments… read them below or add one }

avatar Jason March 30, 2011 at 2:55 pm

A related discussion is currently going on about the Evangelical take on natural law:
http://www.firstthings.com/blogs/firstthoughts/2011/03/28/evangelicals-and-natural-law-update/

avatar Hermonta Godwin May 22, 2011 at 1:28 am

It seems that Kozinski waffles back in forth concerning if one can transcend their religious, historical situatedness or not. If one cannot then one should just stop talking about the concept etc of natural law. If one can, then the project of a publically reasonable moral philosophy is a worthwhile and proper one.

Leave a Comment

Previous post:

Next post: